Over the last two decades, there has been excessive discussion about functional movement training (amusing parody here). The problem with the discussion is not that it’s excessive or sensational but that it obscures some of the emerging principles that define functional movement as a practice. While practices of function movement are rich and prosperous, the conceptual resources available to understand them are not. Using the conceptual tools I outline in Part One, I argue that functional movement practitioners should make aesthetics a defining aim of their practice.
We Don’t Care about Looks, We Care About Feeling Healthy
The current most accepted way of defining functional movement is “prehabilitation.” This is a tremendously empowering way to think about movement. I want to live in a world where people are not only encouraged to find movement-based vocations but are also imagined to require it. I want a world where movement is not considered a matter of choice but rather, a basic necessity. Better still, we need a world where movement-accessible infrastructures and institutions (architectural and social) are not enforced by law but curated with creativity and innovation. Prehabilitation is a very promising way to conceptualize movement but, as the defining aspect of functional movement practices, it is not without its limitations.The more we learn about how a movement practice becomes successful, the more prehabilitation seems unfit for our raison d'ĂȘtre. For example, prehabilitation is difficult to imagine as a basis of lifestyle in the same way as performance is for athletes, or adventure is for mountaineers. It also does not work well as a collective endeavor, but seems to focus on the individual practitioner. The main problem with prehabilitation, however, is that it’s difficult to recognise as an effect on the body. In other words, there are very few ways to account for prehabilitation, as athlete do for performance, surfers do for “stoke,” or dancers can with style. Consider the first diagram that I explained in Part One of this blog. Is prehabilitation a performative, experiential or aesthetic kind of bodily effect?
It is almost impossible to answer this question. It is tempting to categorize prehabilitative effects as experiential because preventing injury and illness is ultimately about feeling good, but these are only secondary or corollary consequences of functional movement. Prehabilitation itself is not experienced. Prehabilitation also cannot be performative because it is not an output. The category of aesthetics is also not appropriate because the bio-physiological mechanism that manifest as “prehabilitation” are not themselves appreciated in an aesthetic register. There are no easy ways to make sense of prehabilitation itself as a kind of bodily effect.
But prehabilitation may not only be inadequate, it might also be limiting as the defining aim of functional movement. To understand how prehabilitation might undercut the larger aims of the functional movement practice, it is helpful to put both in historical context.
Who Put the Function in Functional Movement?
There are two aspects of functional movement’s history that are crucial for understanding why we don’t typically associate aesthetics with the practice. First, functional movement has explicitly and self-consciously developed in opposition to body building, which is prima facie about aesthetics. Second, it has implicitly and somewhat unconsciously developed in the shadow of kinesiology, which is committed to the biomechanical “atomization” (see Part One) of the body. I will briefly explain how both have shaped (and continue to shape) the practice of functional movement. In so doing, I am suggesting that we stop allowing these aspects of our practices history to shape the scope of our practice’s future.
Body Building:
To date, functional movement has not been able to decouple the practices that are at the core of body building from the way fitness is commonly understood and practiced. There are a variety of reasons for the resilience of body building as the default form of fitness but consider the following two.
First, there was at least a 50-year period when body building and fitness were both practically and conceptually synonymous. In that time, the tools, techniques and defining principles of body building were deployed in a variety of institutional settings, including the military and schools. Their purpose in these settings were never muscular hypertrophy but always fitness. Only in the last half of the 20th century did these two aims begin to dissimilate.
Second, body building both legitimizes and is legitimized by beauty and gender norms. Although voices speaking against the tyranny of slenderness are getting louder, it will take a long time to disassociate lean body composition with beauty and sexiness. Similarly, muscularity continues to be a predominate (albeit limited) way for men to both express and develop their sense of masculinity. In sum, there are circuits of social relations that extend beyond the realm of fitness that maintain body building’s prevalence.
As advocates of functional movement, we are right to criticize the narrowness and oppressiveness of norms that connect fitness, beauty and gender. However, the purpose of functional movement should not be to denounce these norms but to create new ones. We want norms that enhance the quality of life, and for a much broader range of potential practitioners. Our strong backlash against the kind of norms associated with body building and weight-loss exercising is obscuring more liberatory norms that movement practices can engender.
Kinesiology:
The second important aspect of functional movement’s history is its roots in kinesiology. With the advent of kinesiology, the methods for training the body stopped being determined by the specifics of the task and started being determined by biomechanics of the body. In other words, kinesiology atomizes the body into mechanical functions. The effects of this conceptual shift cannot be overstated, but there is one change that is particularly relevant for functional movement. We tend to think about the ability to move proficiently as a pyramid. At the base of the pyramid are the foundations of movement abilities, which allow an athlete to build more specialized abilities on top.
On one hand, functional movement rejects the pyramid model in so far as it actively resists the necessity to build the pyramid vertically. In a sense, the goal of functional movement is to create a very wide and stable foundation. On the other hand, functional movement only partially rejects the pyramid model. We still imagine that we are, in fact, building foundations. This makes it difficult to find ways to practice movement, just for the sake of it. That’s our slogan. That’s what we are about. We move because it’s a great way to live.
In sum, we are letting body building and kinesiology delineate the scope of our practice. Unless we stop defining functional movement as ¬not body building, and recognize that our practice can be much more than the handmaiden of kinesiology, then the practice will never amount to more than a type of workout. The key is to decide how functional movement can best effect the body. Although the practice will inevitably produce a mix of performative, experiential and aesthetic bodily effects, there must be ways to approach the practice with one or two types of effects in mind. My argument is that aesthetics should be the defining aim of functional movement training. We need to unapologetically strive to develop movement in an aesthetic register.
Prehabilitation is a Side-Effect of Movement Aesthetics.
In Balance Class several Tuesdays past, the guy training beside me asked himself aloud how learning to handstand with good form was going to improve his cycling. We all laughed because it was near the end of session, and the handstands were becoming increasingly difficult to execute.
If I were a kinesiologists, I might answer him by explaining the benefits of core strength for cycling, or how learning to stabilize the spine will ultimately improve his performance. Then again, I might say that handstands won’t help, and recommend lower-body exercises. Both answers are probably correct, kinesiologically speaking; however, neither reflect the ideas that motivate functional movement. So, what are those ideas?
As a practitioner of functional movement, I want to tell my cyclist friend that learning to handstand with exceptional form is a way of becoming a more proficient mover. The exact biomechanical connection between handstands and cycling is irrelevant. What matters is that both are different forms of bodily movement. While it can be helpful to approach cycling as a means to effect the body’s capacity for endurance or speed, the best way to think about handstands is a means to effect bodily form. By training the body to hold a vertical posture upside down, you are becoming a proficient mover.
Why become a proficient mover? This is a question people need to answer for themselves. There are many ways to lead a meaningful life but, in my opinion, few provide the grace of a life devoted to movement.